Words and Definitions

In this lesson, we will see some words and definitions, along with examples for clarity.

Socrates probably  has a beardSocrates, probably has a beard!

Throughout these lessons, you will encounter words like "Validity", "Reliability", "Argument", "Refutation"..etc. But you may find it difficult to distinguish between them.

First, let's start with the words "Argument" and "Evidence".

1. Argument and Evidence

You may have heard some people using the words "argument" and "evidence" as synonyms, whereas in fact these are very different words, that have different uses.

An argument is a structure that starts with premises and ends with one or more conclusions, that is what an argument is all about. Arguments can be valid, invalid, sound, unsound, reliable or unreliable.

Example of an Argument :
Premise 1: Socrates is a Greek.
Premise 2: All Greeks have beards.
Conclusion: Socrates has a beard.

So, what makes it an argument? simple : it has Premises (Premise 1, Premise 2), and a conclusion. Regardless of whether premises or the conclusion are true or false, That is what an argument is.

Arguments can be Deductive, Inductive or Abductive arguments .. And an argument maybe deductive and inductive at the same time.

The first argument is a Deductive Argument, in that it has Premise 1, Premise 2, and a conclusion .. And we may also consider it an Inductive Argument, in that we can verify Premise 1 and 2 inductivly, by means of observation, to determine whether Socrates has a beard, or whether all Greeks have beards, and to conclude whether the conclusion is probably true or false.

So, to some extent, we can consider some Deductive Arguments to be also Inductive Arguments. You can think of our argument this way inductively :

  • Premise 1: Socrates is a Greek (Inductively Probably True, because most records and accounts about Socrates refer to him as a Greek, and his name is a Greek name).
  • Premise 2: All Greeks have beards. (Inductively False, because many Greeks today apparently do not have beards, and many statues of ancient Greeks have no beards, therefore the statement is false).
  • Conclusion: Socrates has a beard. (The statement is probably Inductively True, since we have statues, paintings and references depicting Socrates as a man with a beard, therefore we know that this is probably True).

Notice that our argument, although deductively valid, has one inductively false premise (Premise 2), and this does not make the conclusion necessarily inductively false. Which means that the relationship between induction and deduction is very tricky.

Syllogism 1:
s is G
All G is B
∴ s is B

So, if you go back to our argument, and study it deductively, you could confirm that it is indeed a valid argument, by looking at its syllogistic form (Syllogism 1).

But if you study it inductively, then you could confirm that one of its premises is false, although the conclusion is probably True (Syllogism 2).

I hope you see what I mean. Now let us talk about the word "Evidence".

Syllogism 2 (same syllogism but with inductive notices):
s is G (probably True)
All G is B (False)
∴ s is B (probably True)

Evidence is an inductive and scientific word. If you consider a statement True (for example the first premise in our argument : Socrates is Greek), then you should provide evidence that can prove the statement is inductively "probably" True.

And, unlike arguments which can have false premises or conclusions. Evidence cannot, by any means, be false and still be refered to as "Evidence".

Evidence is, epistemologically speaking, a very strong word, and a rational agent ought to utilize this word cautiously.

Always use the word "argument" when talking about a structure that consists of "premises" and "conclusions", regardless of their truth value. And do NOT use the word "evidence" unless you have statements that are considered TRUE and RELIABLE by all the parties involved in the argumentation or discussion (especially, scientific or factual evidence).

Example that uses evidence :
Premise 1: IF Genetic comparisons and the fossil record point to the fact that species appear slowly and gradually while respecting a certain order AND are genetically related as evolution predicts. THEN Evolution is probably True.
Premise 2: Genetic comparisons and the fossil record point to the fact that species appear slowly and gradually while respecting a certain order AND are genetically related as evolution predicts.
Conclusion: Evolution is probably True.
The fossil record supports evolutionThe fossil record supports evolution because it is what evolutonary theory predicts, and by abduction, any other explanation would be more complex than the evolution of life by means of natural selection.

Let us look into this argument in detail.

Premise 1: IF Genetic comparisons and the fossil record point to the fact that species appear slowly and gradually while respecting a certain order AND are genetically related as evolution predicts. THEN Evolution is probably True.

This statement is a conditional statement, since it consists of an "if ... then".

It is a deductive premise. In that it does not say anything about whether "Genetic comparisons and the fossil record point to the fact that species appear slowly and gradually while respecting a certain order" or that "they are genetically related", or that "evolution is probably true". It just establishes a conditional relationship between genetics, species' appearence in the fossil record, and evolution's reliability based on its predictions.

Since it is a deductive premise, you may or may not agree with it. But your disagreement would not be reasonable by means of abductive reasoning as we will see in the next lesson (Hint : the premise is probably true, as it appeals to the simplest explanation, using Occam's Razor, so you cannot, abductively speaking, refute it unless you provide a better and less complex explanation, that's what abduction is all about).

Premise 2: Genetic comparisons and the fossil record point to the fact that species appear slowly and gradually while respecting a certain order AND are genetically related as evolution predicts.

This premise is an inductive statement, you cannot refute it because we know, inductively, that this is probably true, since we have irrefutable strong evidence, that is: these are pieces of "evidence" and you cannot reject them.

So, as we said, evidence is always probably True, it cannot be false, because it is scientific, there are observations and experiments, that make it reasonable to consider this premise as strong evidence.

Conclusion: Evolution is probably True.

This is an inductive conclusion, evolution is "probably" true (like 90-99% certainty), because we know that:

  • - Premise 1 is probably true (by abduction).
  • - Premise 2 is probably true (by induction, since these are pieces of inductive observational and experimental evidence).

Therefore, the conclusion is probably true (by deduction, You can check its validity, we have a Modus Ponens here and we will see what that means later).

As I said, in the next lesson we will see why the first premise is probably true by abduction.

2. Validity, Reliability, Soundness and Truth :

Now, let us talk about validity, reliability, soundness and truth. As well as their opposites, respectively : Invalidity, Unreliability, Unsoundness and Falsehood.

Validity and Invalidity of a deductive argument:

An argument is valid, if and only if, deductively speaking, its conclusion follows from its premises. Our two previous arguments are deductively valid. And vice versa, an argument is deductively invalid, if the premises, collectively, do not imply the conclusion.

Reliability and Unreliability of an inductive argument:

An argument is reliable, if and only if, inductively speaking, all its premises are probably true, and the conclusion is probably true . Regardless of whether it is valid or not.

So, An argument can be :
- Deductively valid and inductively reliable.
- Deducively valid, but inductively unreliable.
- Deductively invalid, but inductively reliable.
- Deductively invalid and inductively unreliable.

Which means that what follows logically, does not imply reliability or truth. And what does not follow logically, does not imply unreliability or falsehood.

As we can see, reliability has nothing to do with validity. Validity concerns what is "logical" or "deductively consistent". And reliability concerns what is probably True or False.

Which means that you can have logically valid arguments, but none of your premises or conclusions is probably True.

For example :
Premise 1: If Unicorns exist then they look beautiful.
Premise 2: Unicorns exist.
Conclusion: Therefore, they are beautiful.

The argument above is deductively valid, since premises imply the conclusion. But it is inductively unreliable because we do not have any evidence backing the second premise.

So far we saw Validity and Reliability, but what is Soundness.

A sound argument is an argument which combines both : deductive validity and inductive reliability, which means that All premises and the conclusion are inductively probably true, AND the conclusion follows from the premises.

Example of a sound argument :
Permise 1: If ships disappear over the horizon, then the earth has a curvature.
Premise 2: Ships disappear over the horizon.
Conclusion: Therefore, the earth has a curvature.

The argument is sound, because we have a Modus Ponens (of the form, if P then Q, P, therefore Q). And Premise 2 is inductively true, and the conclusion is inductively probably true.

If the argument is reliable but invalid, or valid but inreliable, or both, then it is an unsound argument.

Example of an unsound argument:
Premise 1: If the earth is flat, then ships do not disappear over the horizon.
Premise 2: the earth is flat.
Conclusion: Therefore, Ships do not disappear over the horizon.

This is also a Modus Ponens, like the previous argument. But unlike the sound argument, the second premise and the conclusion do not hold inductively, they are unreliable. Therefore, the argument, although, deductively valid, is inductively unreliable. Which makes it an unsound argument.

Now, what do "True" and "False" mean?

Unlike the other notions, we cannot say that an "argument" is true or false, for we can only say that a statement is true or false.

A statement or proposition is true, if and only if, its claim matches an event or a state of affairs in some actual world.

A statement or proposition is false, if and only if, its claim does not match any event or state of affairs in all actual world.

What it means, is that, whether we know it or not, or whether we have evidence or not, a statement is true if it projects on reality, even if that reality is in another Universe or world.

That is what "truth" is about. Inductively speaking, we can prove some statement is true or false.

So, that is what truth and falsehood are all about.

3. Proof and Refutation:

Proof and Refutation are two concepts that are used to appraise inductive statements, to prove a statement, means that you have evidence to back it, that shows that there is a good reason to think that such or such statement is probably inductively true.

For instance, "ships disappearing over the horizon" is a proof, or proves that the earth is curved. While the same statement is a refutation, or refutes the claim that it is flat.

Finally, let's talk about what makes a Good Argument:

A good argument is an argument that fullfills the following requirements:

  • It has to be deductively valid (The conclusion follows from the premises).
  • It has the premises as evident as possible to all the parties invovled in the argumentation.
  • Its premises are inductively reliable.
  • It avoids ambiguity, amphiboly, emotional biases, or any informal or formal fallacies.
  • It is relevant to the subject matter.

The opposite of a good argument, is a bad argument.

Ships do indeed disappear over the horizon, in normal weather conditions (normal temperature, pressure..etc), which makes a good evidence for earth's curvature.
Example of a good argument:
Permise 1: If ships disappear over the horizon, then the earth has a curvature.
Premise 2: Ships disappear over the horizon.
Conclusion: Therefore, the earth has a curvature.

The argument is good because, it is a Modus Ponens (hence deductively valid), the premises are very evident to rational persons, except if they are ignorant, then we should show them that the premises are probably true..

It is also a good argument, because the premises are reliable, and it avoids ambiguity and amphiboly in that we know exactly what the words mean. We also know that it avoids the appeal to emotions since we don't have any emotional language used in the premises or conclusion.

It is relevant to the subject matter as long as we are arguing about the shape of the earth, and not about shakespear's Hamlet.

And finally, we can confirm that it does not commit any informal or formal fallacies that we know of. (we will see hundreds of formal and informal fallacies in future lessons).

That's it for this lesson, in the next lesson we will take an in-depth look at abductive reasoning, along with examples to make it as clear as possible.