Inductive Reasoning

Inductive Reasoning is concerned with the probability of a statement being True or False, Unlike Deductive Reasoning, Induction uses empirical and observational tools to derive conclusions, about how probable a certain outcome is. Basically, Inductive Reasoning, helps us build predictive models about the future, based on past experience.

CiceroCicero, one of the first philosophers to mention "Induction".

Induction is not only used in science, but also in daily life. For example : You can’t eat poison because you know it will probably kill you, based on past experience and knowledge.

Without contact with the outside world there is no way to know that poison kills, for instance an infant does not have this type of empirical knowledge, but as adults, we know that it is very probable that some substances are harmful.

Remember:
Induction does NOT give you 100% certainty  … it can be 60%, 70%, 90%, 99.99% … but NOT 100%.

Another simple, yet classical example : We know, by induction, that the sun will probably rise tomorrow, because it did for billions of years.

We said in the previous lesson that the argument is deductively valid … yet, we cannot determine whether the premises or conclusion are true without induction, we have to make observations and experiments to check if the first premise holds, for example.

Using observation (which is also an inductive tool),  we know that there are winged animals that don’t fly (examples : ostriches, chickens...etc). Therefore, by induction : the first premise is false.

Back to our argument :
Premise 1: All Winged Animals Fly
Premie 2: Pegasi are Winged Animals
Conclusion:Therefore, Pegasi Fly

Of course, we don’t need to check the second premise and the conclusion, but I think it would be interesting to check if they hold.

The second premise : “Pegasi are winged animals”. Is that statement True or False?

You may be inclined to say that the statement is False, since you “think” that an animal such a Pegasus does not exist.

But, remember : the statement does NOT assert that Pegasi exist. For it only assigns the predicate “winged animal” to the subject “Pegasus”, and that is all.

Unfortunately this type of statement (which is called an Analytic Statement) is usually known A priori. (we will come to A priori / A posteriori and Analytic / Synthetic  distinctions later).

That is, you don’t need observation or experiments to know that “Pegasus is a Winged Animal”. Because it is True, by definition, that Pegasi are Winged Mythical  Animals, Regardless of their existence.

Pegasi and UnicornsI am not saying that Pegasi or Unicorns don't exist, so they should be okay for now.

I am not saying that Pegasi exist, I am saying that as far as induction is concerned, we must distinguish between two types of statements :

  • Pegasi are Winged Animals
  • Pegasi Exist

The first statement is just a definition: according to Greek mythology, Pegasus is a winged horse, hence a winged animal. So, by definition, the statement is True.

But the second statement, “Pegasi Exist” is not a definition (and it is a synthetic, not an analytics statement), Therefore, To prove that Pegasus exists, we need to observe, or to find, at least one animal that meets the requirements that make it qualified to be a Pegasus.

Does it mean Pegasi do Not exist? No because, Inductively speaking, to prove the statement "Pegasi exist" … You need to find one single entity that is a Pegasus.

But, to refute the statement "Pegasi exist", is even more difficult and complicated : You will need to look in all actual worlds (in other words, in all existence, in all actual planets, galaxies,  universes), and if you did not find any Pegasus, therefore Pegasi do not exist.

Back to our argument :
Premise 1: All Winged Animals Fly
Premie 2: Pegasi are Winged Animals
Conclusion:Therefore, Pegasi Fly
  • We know, by induction, that Premise 1 is probably False.
  • We know, by definition, that Premise 2 is True.

What about the conclusion?

 As for the conclusion, we do not know if it is true or false, all we know is that the whole argument is unsound (because at least the first premise is inductively false).

Let’s try and correct our argument using induction, we know that the premise “All winged animals Fly” is false.

To correct this premise, we will have to make a small change : instead of using “all”, let us use the more accurate “some” : Some Winged Animals Fly.

So, let’s see what our conclusion would look like now :

Premise 1: Some Winged Animals Fly
Premie 2: Pegasi are Winged Animals
Conclusion:Therefore, Some Pegasi Fly 

As you can see, we used Induction to change “All” to “Some”, in the first premise, and the conclusion.

That makes our first premise True. But does it make our argument any better? NO … Why ?

Because, now, Although :

  • Premise 1 is True, (By Induction), since "some winged animals fly".
  • Premise 2 is True, (By Definition), since "Pegasi are winged animals".

Our argument is now Invalid (By deduction). 

Did you make a realization yet?

We corrected our inductively false premise, and added "some", to make it True ... And we used our "intuition" to conclude that only "Some" Pegasi should be able to fly.

But this made our Argument Invalid (By Deduction). 

Let's Show how our Argument (Before the Correction) is deductively valid, although inductively unsound:

To see what I mean, let’s go back to our first argument (before the correction). And draw its Venn Diagram (it is not really an official Venn Diagram, but it will help us here).

"All Winged Animals Fly" : Let’s draw a circle "F" for all things that “Fly” .

Now, Let’s draw the circle of “Winged Animals” inside it, to represent the premise “all winged animals fly”.

Now, let’s draw a circle "P" for "Pegasi" inside the "Winged Animals", to represent the premise “All Pegasi are Winged Animals”.

All Flying Animals - Venn diagramWe first draw a circle "F" representing all things that "Fly".
All Winged Animals - Venn diagramThen, we draw a circle "W" representing all things that are "Winged Animals".
All Pegasi are Winged Animals - Venn diagramFinally, we draw a circle "P" representing all things that are "Winged Pegasi"
 

As you can see, the circle “Pegasi” is inside the circle "Fly", therefore, we can conclude that "All Pegasi do Fly". 

But we know by Induction, that the premise “all winged animals fly”, therefore we should change it to : “some winged animals fly”.

And you may agree, by intuition, that we are inclined to change “all” to “some” in the conclusion too. Now let’s draw the Venn Diagram.

Let's Show how our Argument (After the correction) is deductively invalid, although the first premise is now inductively reliable:

We know that “some winged animals fly”, now let’s draw a circle to represent all flying animals.

 

Good, Now, since some winged animals fly, we cannot draw the circle “winged animals” inside the circle fly, only a part of the two circles should overlap, this area, the intersection between the two circles, represents the things that are “Winged Animals” and “Fly”.

All Flying Animals - Venn diagramWe, again, draw a circle "F" representing all things that "Fly".
Winged-Flying intersection - Venn diagramThe intersection WF, winged animals that fly


Now, The second premise asserts that "Pegasi are Winged Animals"… we have 3 possibilities as to where to draw the circle that represents Pegasi .

  1. If we draw it inside “Winged Animals” but not “Flying Animals” circle, then the conclusion would be “All Pegasi are winged animals, but do not fly”. 
  2. If we draw it inside the intersection between the two circles , then the conclusion would be “All Pegasi are winged animals that fly”.
  3. If we draw part of it inside the intersection, and part of it outside, then the conclusion would be “Some pegasi are winged animals that fly”, which is our conclusion, after making a somehow intuitive correction.
No Pegasi Fly - Venn diagramPossible conclusion 1 : No Pegasi Fly.
All Pegasi fly - Venn diagramPossible conclusion 2 : All Pegasi fly.
Some Pegasi Fly - Venn diagramPossible conclusion 3 : Some Pegasi Fly, which matches our conclusion

As you can see, we cannot conclude “Some pegasi fly” directly, it seems like you need something else to reach that conclusion, therefore our argument is Deductively Invalid.

To sum up : 

  1. An inductively reliable argument, is not necessarily a deductively valid argument.
  2. Using intuition alone to correct an inductive argument, using induction, does not make it necessarily deductively valid.
  3. A deductively valid argument, may or may not have inductively true premises.

In future lessons, we will see rules of logic to appraise different arguments, and NO , intuition does not always work like we saw in this lesson, and that is how studying logic is tricky, and fun for that matter.

I hope you learned the difference between Inductive and Deductive Reasoning. In the next lesson we will look into different definitions like : Validity, Soundness, Reliability...etc.